Zeno's paradoxes: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Content deleted Content added
{{failed verification|date=March 2010|sources do not say "with high accuracy", they say the mathematical aspects have been solved}}
Proposed solutions: preuming consensus, I moved quote into citation per [http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Talk%3AZeno%27s_paradoxes&action=historysubmit&diff=347212142&oldid=347211785]
Line 113: Line 113:
Another proposed solution<ref name=boyer/><ref>{{cite journal |url=http://www.jstor.org/pss/187807 |title=Discussion:Zeno's Paradoxes and the Tile Argument |first=Jean Paul |last=van Bendegem |location= Belgium |year=1987 |journal=Philosophy of Science |volume=54 |pages=295-302 |accessdate=2010-02-27}}</ref> is to question the assumption inherent in Zeno's paradox, which is that between any two different points in space (or time), there is always another point. Without this assumption there are only a finite number of distances between two points, hence there is no infinite sequence of movements, and the paradox is resolved.
Another proposed solution<ref name=boyer/><ref>{{cite journal |url=http://www.jstor.org/pss/187807 |title=Discussion:Zeno's Paradoxes and the Tile Argument |first=Jean Paul |last=van Bendegem |location= Belgium |year=1987 |journal=Philosophy of Science |volume=54 |pages=295-302 |accessdate=2010-02-27}}</ref> is to question the assumption inherent in Zeno's paradox, which is that between any two different points in space (or time), there is always another point. Without this assumption there are only a finite number of distances between two points, hence there is no infinite sequence of movements, and the paradox is resolved.


[[Rudy Rucker]] has mentioned a possible solution to Zeno's arrow paradox. Rucker notes that, in contrast to Zeno's assumption, the length of an arrow at rest differs from an arrow in motion due to the [[special theory of relativity|relativistic]] effect of [[Lorentz–Fitzgerald contraction|length contraction]]:
[[Rudy Rucker]] has mentioned a possible solution to Zeno's arrow paradox. Rucker notes that, in contrast to Zeno's assumption, the length of an arrow at rest differs from an arrow in motion due to the [[special theory of relativity|relativistic]] effect of [[Lorentz–Fitzgerald contraction|length contraction]], which makes the state of motion "instantaneously observable".<ref name="Rucker">{{cite book |title=Infinity and the Mind: The Science and Philosophy of the Infinite |last=Rucker |first=Rudy von Bitter |authorlink=Rudy Rucker |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=Y8H243Z2GTQC&q=Infinity+and+the+Mind&dq=Infinity+and+the+Mind&cd=1 |year=1983 |page=264 |publisher=Bantam Books |isbn=0553234331 |accessdate=28 February 2010|quote=There actually is a way out of [Zeno's argument] that I have never seen published: According to Special Relativity, an arrow in motion experiences a relativistic length contraction proportional to its speed. So, in fact, the arrow's state of motion ''is'' instantaneously observable!<!-- NOTE: In Rucker's book, this entire quote in found within parentheses. - Paine Ellsworth -->}}</ref>

{{quote|There actually is a way out of [Zeno's argument] that I have never seen published: According to Special Relativity, an arrow in motion experiences a relativistic length contraction proportional to its speed. So, in fact, the arrow's state of motion ''is'' instantaneously observable!<!-- NOTE: In Rucker's book, this entire quote in found within parentheses. - Paine Ellsworth --><ref name="Rucker">{{cite book |title=Infinity and the Mind: The Science and Philosophy of the Infinite |last=Rucker |first=Rudy von Bitter |authorlink=Rudy Rucker |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=Y8H243Z2GTQC&q=Infinity+and+the+Mind&dq=Infinity+and+the+Mind&cd=1 |year=1983 |page=264 |publisher=Bantam Books |isbn=0553234331 |accessdate=28 February 2010}}</ref>}}


=== Physics ===
=== Physics ===

Revision as of 02:06, 2 March 2010

squares shown at 45 degree angles, some black and some white, one black square filled with smaller squares, red silhouette of young girl walking up one edge, red silhouette of small turtle walking down an edge
A fractal used to explain the paradoxes of Zeno of Elea— a movement can become impossible if its distance is recurrently divided into smaller pieces

Zeno's paradoxes are a set of problems generally thought to have been devised by Zeno of Elea to support Parmenides's doctrine that "all is one" and that, contrary to the evidence of our senses, the belief in plurality and change is mistaken, and in particular that motion is nothing but an illusion. It is usually assumed, based on Plato's Parmenides 128c-d, that Zeno took on the project of creating these paradoxes because other philosophers had created paradoxes against Parmenides's view. Thus Zeno can be interpreted as saying that to assume there is plurality is even more absurd than assuming there is only "the One" (Parmenides 128d). Plato makes Socrates claim that Zeno and Parmenides were essentially arguing exactly the same point (Parmenides 128a-b).

Several of Zeno's nine surviving paradoxes (preserved in Aristotle's Physics[1] and Simplicius's commentary thereon) are essentially equivalent to one another; and most of them were regarded, even in ancient times, as very easy to refute [1]. Three of the strongest and most famous—that of Achilles and the tortoise, the Dichotomy argument, and that of an arrow in flight—are presented in detail below.

Zeno's arguments are perhaps the first examples of a method of proof called reductio ad absurdum also known as proof by contradiction. They are also credited as a source of the dialectic method used by Socrates.[2]

While more modern calculus has solved the mathematical aspects of the paradox with high-accuracy,[3][4][5][failed verification] Zeno's paradoxes remain a major problem for philosophers.[6][7][8] Variations on the paradoxes (see Thomson's lamp) continue to produce philosophically and mathematically challenging problems.

The origins of the paradoxes are somewhat unclear. Diogenes Laertius, citing Favorinus, says that Zeno's teacher Parmenides, was the first to introduce the Achilles and the Tortoise Argument. But in a later passage, Laertius attributes the origin of the paradox to Zeno, explaining that Favorinus disagrees.[9]

The Paradoxes of Motion

Achilles and the tortoise

In a race, the quickest runner can never overtake the slowest, since the pursuer must first reach the point whence the pursued started, so that the slower must always hold a lead.

— Aristotle, Physics VI:9, 239b15

In the paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise, Achilles is in a footrace with the tortoise. Achilles allows the tortoise a head start of 100 metres. If we suppose that each racer starts running at some constant speed (one very fast and one very slow), then after some finite time, Achilles will have run 100 metres, bringing him to the tortoise's starting point. During this time, the tortoise has run a much shorter distance, say, 10 metres. It will then take Achilles some further time to run that distance, by which time the tortoise will have advanced farther; and then more time still to reach this third point, while the tortoise moves ahead. Thus, whenever Achilles reaches somewhere the tortoise has been, he still has farther to go. Therefore, because there are an infinite number of points Achilles must reach where the tortoise has already been, he can never overtake the tortoise. Of course, simple experience tells us that Achilles will be able to overtake the tortoise, which is why this is a paradox.[10][11]

The dichotomy paradox

That which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage before it arrives at the goal.

— Aristotle, Physics VI:9, 239b10

Suppose Homer wants to catch a stationary bus. Before he can get there, he must get halfway there. Before he can get halfway there, he must get a quarter of the way there. Before traveling a fourth, he must travel one-eighth; before an eighth, one-sixteenth; and so on.

The resulting sequence can be represented as:

This description requires one to complete an infinite number of tasks, which Zeno maintains is an impossibility.

This sequence also presents a second problem in that it contains no first distance to run, for any possible (finite) first distance could be divided in half, and hence would not be first after all. Hence, the trip cannot even begin. The paradoxical conclusion then would be that travel over any finite distance can neither be completed nor begun, and so all motion must be an illusion.

This argument is called the Dichotomy because it involves repeatedly splitting a distance into two parts. It contains some of the same elements as the Achilles and the Tortoise paradox, but with a more apparent conclusion of motionlessness. It is also known as the Race Course paradox. Some, like Aristotle, regard the Dichotomy as really just another version of Achilles and the Tortoise.[12]

The arrow paradox

If everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest, and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless.

— Aristotle, Physics VI:9, 239b5

In the arrow paradox (also known as the fletcher's paradox), Zeno states that for motion to be occurring, an object must change the position which it occupies. He gives an example of an arrow in flight. He states that in any one instant of time, for the arrow to be moving it must either move to where it is, or it must move to where it is not. However, it cannot move to where it is not, because this is a single instant, and it cannot move to where it is because it is already there. In other words, in any instant of time there is no motion occurring, because an instant is a snapshot. Therefore, if it cannot move in a single instant it cannot move in any instant, making any motion impossible.

Whereas the first two paradoxes presented divide space, this paradox starts by dividing time—and not into segments, but into points.[13]

Three other paradoxes as given by Aristotle

Paradox of Place:

"… if everything that exists has a place, place too will have a place, and so on ad infinitum."[14]

Paradox of the Grain of Millet:

"… there is no part of the millet that does not make a sound: for there is no reason why any such part should not in any length of time fail to move the air that the whole bushel moves in falling. In fact it does not of itself move even such a quantity of the air as it would move if this part were by itself: for no part even exists otherwise than potentially."[15]

The Moving Rows:

"The fourth argument is that concerning the two rows of bodies, each row being composed of an equal number of bodies of equal size, passing each other on a race-course as they proceed with equal velocity in opposite directions, the one row originally occupying the space between the goal and the middle point of the course and the other that between the middle point and the starting-post. This...involves the conclusion that half a given time is equal to double that time."[16]

For an expanded account of Zeno's arguments as presented by Aristotle, see Simplicius' commentary On Aristotle's Physics.

Proposed solutions

Aristotle (384 BC−322 BC) remarked that as the distance decreases, the time needed to cover those distances also decreases, so that the time needed also becomes increasingly small.[17] Aristotle's proposed solution for the paradoxes involves distinguishing "things infinite in respect of divisibility" (such as a unit of space that can be mentally divided into ever smaller units while remaining spatially the same) from things (or distances) that are infinite in extension ("with respect to their extremities").[18]

Before 212 BC, Archimedes had developed a method to derive a finite answer for the sum of infinitely many terms that get progressively smaller. (See: Geometric series, 1/4 + 1/16 + 1/64 + 1/256 + · · ·, The Quadrature of the Parabola.) Modern calculus achieves the same result, using more rigorous methods (see convergent series, where the "reciprocals of powers of 2" series, equivalent to the Dichotomy Paradox, is listed as convergent). These methods allow construction of solutions stating that under suitable conditions (i.e. the distances are progressively decreasing), the travel time is finite (bounded by a fixed upper bound).[19][3]

Another proposed solution[3][20] is to question the assumption inherent in Zeno's paradox, which is that between any two different points in space (or time), there is always another point. Without this assumption there are only a finite number of distances between two points, hence there is no infinite sequence of movements, and the paradox is resolved.

Rudy Rucker has mentioned a possible solution to Zeno's arrow paradox. Rucker notes that, in contrast to Zeno's assumption, the length of an arrow at rest differs from an arrow in motion due to the relativistic effect of length contraction, which makes the state of motion "instantaneously observable".[21]

Physics

In the 18th and 19th centuries, the Newtonian model (also known as classical mechanics) was the most prominent theory explaining the motion of bodies. In the Newtonian model space and time are infinitely divisible—that is, between any two given points there exists another point—and all particles and bodies occupy specific points in space at specific points in time. In this model, the exact point when Achilles overtakes the tortoise can be found by calculating the sum of a geometric series.

By the early 20th century, the Newtonian model was discovered to be inaccurate for describing certain microscopic events, for example the movements of electrons. A competing theory, quantum mechanics, gained acceptance as a more accurate description of how bodies behave. In the most widely held interpretation of quantum mechanics, particles do not occupy specific points in space at specific points in time, rather, the probability of observing a particle in a certain interval of space during a certain interval of time follows a probability distribution generated by the particle's wave function. In this model, neither the exact time nor the exact place when Achilles overtakes the tortoise can be calculated, since neither the place nor the time are deterministic but stochastic. However, the expectation values of the point (and time) where Achilles overtakes the tortoise can be calculated exactly. According to the Ehrenfest theorem these expectation values are equal to the ones found in the solution for the Newtonian model.[22] Because of the size of Achilles and the tortoise, their respective variances are very low, and the differences between the two models will be negligible.

Status of the paradoxes today

Infinite processes remained theoretically troublesome in mathematics until the early 20th century. The epsilon-delta version of Weierstrass and Cauchy (or the equivalent and equally rigorous differential/infinitesimal version by Abraham Robinson), have developed a rigorous formulation of the logic and calculus involved. These works have resolved the mathematics involving infinite processes, including Zeno's, and the paradoxes no longer present any mathematical problems[23][4].

While mathematics can be used to calculate where and when the moving Achilles will overtake the Tortoise of Zeno's paradox, which when applied to the motion of physical bodies gives highly accurate predictions [23][4][24][25], some philosophers[6][7]say that the mathematics does not address the central point in Zeno's argument, and that solving the mathematical issues does not solve every issue the paradoxes present. Philosophers[who?] also remark that Zeno's arguments are often misrepresented in the popular literature. That is, Zeno is often said to have argued that the sum of an infinite number of terms must itself be infinite - that both the distance and the time to be travelled are infinite. However, Zeno's problem was not with finding the sum of an infinite sequence, but rather with finishing an infinite number of tasks: how can one ever get from A to B, if an infinite number of events can be identified that need to precede the arrival at B, and one cannot reach even the beginning of a "last event"? Philosophers[6][4][7][8][26] say that calculus does not address that question, and hence a solution to Zeno's paradoxes must be found elsewhere. Philosophers[6][7][8] do not see how mathematics takes anything away from Zeno's reasoning that there are problems in explaining how motion can happen at all.

In the field of verification and design of timed and hybrid systems, the system behaviour is called Zeno if it includes an infinite number of discrete steps in a finite amount of time. Many formal verification techniques exclude these behaviours from analysis, if they are not equivalent to non-Zeno behaviour. In systems design these behaviours will also often be excluded from system models, since they cannot be implemented with a digital controller.

The quantum Zeno effect

In 1977,[27] physicists E. C. G. Sudarshan and B. Misra studying quantum mechanics discovered that the dynamical evolution (motion) of a quantum system can be hindered (or even inhibited) through observation of the system.[28] This effect is usually called the "quantum Zeno effect" as it is strongly reminiscent of Zeno's arrow paradox.

This effect was first theorized in 1958.[29]

Writings about Zeno’s paradoxes

artist's rendering of sculpted bust of man with thin face and medium-length beard
Zeno[citation needed] of Elea

Zeno’s paradoxes have inspired many writers

  • Leo Tolstoy in War and Peace (Part 11,Chapter I) discusses the race of Achilles and the tortoise when critiquing "historical science".
  • In the dialogue What the Tortoise Said to Achilles, Lewis Carroll describes what happens at the end of the race. The tortoise discusses with Achilles a simple deductive argument. Achilles fails in demonstrating the argument because the tortoise leads him into an infinite regression.
  • In Gödel, Escher, Bach by Douglas Hofstadter, the various chapters are separated by dialogues between Achilles and the tortoise, inspired by Lewis Carroll’s works
  • The Argentinian writer Jorge Luis Borges discusses Zeno’s paradoxes many times in his work, showing their relationship with infinity. Borges also used Zeno’s paradoxes as a metaphor for some situations described by Kafka.
  • Paul Hornschemeier's most recent graphic novel, The Three Paradoxes, contains a comic version of Zeno presenting his three paradoxes to his fellow philosophers.
  • Leslie Lamport's Specifying Systems contains a section (9.4) introducing the character of the Zeno Specifications
  • Zadie Smith references Zeno's arrow paradox, and, more briefly, Zeno's Achilles and tortoise paradox, at the end of Chapter 17 in her novel White Teeth.
  • Brian Massumi shoots Zeno's "philosophical arrow" in the opening chapter of Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation.
  • Philip K. Dick's short science-fiction story "The Indefatigable Frog" concerns an experiment to determine whether a frog which continually leaps half the distance to the top of a well will ever be able to get out of the well.
  • Allama Iqbal's book The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam discusses the paradox in Lecture II The Philosophical Test of the Revelations of Religious Experience, and suggests that motion is not continuous but discrete.
  • Ursula K. Le Guin's character of Shevek in The Dispossessed discusses the arrow paradox in great amusement with his un-understanding classmates as a child.
  • Jorge Luis Borges traces, in an essay entitled "Avatars of the Tortoise", the many recurrences of this paradox in works of philosophy. The successive references he traces are Agrippa the sceptic, Thomas Aquinas, Hermann Lotze, F.H. Bradley and William James.[30]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ a b Aristotle's Physics "Physics" by Aristotle translated by R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye
  2. ^ ([fragment 65], Diogenes Laertius. IX 25ff and VIII 57)
  3. ^ a b c Boyer, Carl (1959). The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development. Dover Publications. Retrieved 26 February 2010.
  4. ^ a b c d Lynds, Peter (2003). "Zeno's Paradoxes: A Timely Solution". Retrieved 24 February 2010.
  5. ^ Zhang, Jun; Johansson, Karl; Lygeros, John; Sastry, Shankar (2001). "Zeno hybrid systems" (PDF). International Journal for Robust and Nonlinear control. Retrieved 2010-02-28.
  6. ^ a b c d Brown, Kevin. "Reflections on Relativity".
  7. ^ a b c d Moorcroft, Francis. "Zeno's Paradox".
  8. ^ a b c Papa-Grimaldi, Alba (1996). "Why Mathematical Solutions of Zeno's Paradoxes Miss the Point: Zeno's One and Many Relation and Parmenides' Prohibition". The Review of Metaphysics. {{cite web}}: Unknown parameter |vol= ignored (|volume= suggested) (help)
  9. ^ Diogenes Laertius, Lives, 9.23 and 9.29.
  10. ^ "Math Forum".
  11. ^ Huggett, Nick (2004), "Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.2 Achilles and the Tortoise", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, retrieved 2009-11-18
  12. ^ Huggett, Nick (2004), "Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.1 The Dichotomy", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, retrieved 2009-11-18
  13. ^ Huggett, Nick (2004), "Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.3 The Arrow", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, retrieved 2009-11-18
  14. ^ Aristotle Physics IV:1, 209a25
  15. ^ Aristotle Physics VII:5, 250a20
  16. ^ Aristotle Physics VI:9, 239b33
  17. ^ Aristotle. Physics 6.9
  18. ^ Aristotle. Physics 6.9; 6.2, 233a21-31
  19. ^ George B. Thomas, Calculus and Analytic Geometry, Addison Wesley, 1951
  20. ^ van Bendegem, Jean Paul (1987). "Discussion:Zeno's Paradoxes and the Tile Argument". Philosophy of Science. 54. Belgium: 295–302. Retrieved 2010-02-27.
  21. ^ Rucker, Rudy von Bitter (1983). Infinity and the Mind: The Science and Philosophy of the Infinite. Bantam Books. p. 264. ISBN 0553234331. Retrieved 28 February 2010. There actually is a way out of [Zeno's argument] that I have never seen published: According to Special Relativity, an arrow in motion experiences a relativistic length contraction proportional to its speed. So, in fact, the arrow's state of motion is instantaneously observable!
  22. ^ Fitzpatrick, Richard (16 February 2006). "Ehrenfest's theorem". Quantum Mechanics: A graduate level course. Austin TX 78712, USA: Institute for Fusion Studies, University of Texas at Austin. Retrieved 22 February 2010. This is known as Ehrenfest's theorem." ... "it guarantees to us that the centre of a wave-packet always moves like a classical particle.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: location (link)
  23. ^ a b Lee, Harold (1965). "Are Zeno's Paradoxes Based on a Mistake?". Mind. 74 (296). Oxford University Press: 563-570. Retrieved 24 February 2010.
  24. ^ "The Free High School Science Texts: Textbooks for High School Students · Studying the Sciences · Mathematics · Grades 10-12" (PDF). FHSST Authors. Version 0 · 17 September 2008. p. 22 (510). Retrieved 12 February 2010. {{cite web}}: Check date values in: |date= (help); External link in |publisher= (help)
  25. ^ "Mathematics Illuminated  · Unit 3.4  · Zeno's Paradoxes". Annenberg media. Retrieved 24 February 2010. {{cite web}}: Cite has empty unknown parameter: |1= (help); External link in |publisher= (help)
  26. ^ Huggett, Nick (2004), "Zeno's Paradoxes: 5. Zeno's Influence on Philosophy", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, retrieved 2009-11-18
  27. ^ Sudarshan, E. C. G.; Misra, B. (1977), "The Zeno's paradox in quantum theory", Journal of Mathematical Physics, 18 (4): 756–763, doi:10.1063/1.523304
  28. ^ W.M.Itano (1990). "Quantum Zeno effect" (PDF). PRA. 41: 2295–2300. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.41.2295. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  29. ^ Khalfin, L.A. (1958), Soviet Phys. JETP, 6: 1053 {{citation}}: Missing or empty |title= (help)
  30. ^ Borges, Jorge Luis (1964). Labyrinths. London: Penguin. pp. 237–243.

References

  • Kirk, G. S., J. E. Raven, M. Schofield (1984) The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts, 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521274559.
  • Huggett, Nick (2004). "Zeno's Paradoxes". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2009-11-18.
  • Plato (1926) Plato: Cratylus. Parmenides. Greater Hippias. Lesser Hippias, H. N. Fowler (Translator), Loeb Classical Library. ISBN 0674991850.
  • Sainsbury, R.M. (2003) Paradoxes, 2nd ed. Cambridge Univ. Press. ISBN 0521483476.

Zeno's paradox at PlanetMath.